In logic, the scope of a quantifier or connective is the shortest formula in which it occurs, determining the range in the formula to which the quantifier or connective is applied. The notions of a free variable and bound variable are defined in terms of whether that formula is within the scope of a quantifier, and the notions of a dominant connective and subordinate connective are defined in terms of whether a connective includes another within its scope.
Connectives
Logical connectives | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Related concepts | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Applications | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Category | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||
The scope of a logical connective occurring within a formula is the smallest well-formed formula that contains the connective in question. The connective with the largest scope in a formula is called its dominant connective, main connective, main operator, major connective, or principal connective; a connective within the scope of another connective is said to be subordinate to it.
For instance, in the formula , the dominant connective is ↔, and all other connectives are subordinate to it; the → is subordinate to the ∨, but not to the ∧; the first ¬ is also subordinate to the ∨, but not to the →; the second ¬ is subordinate to the ∧, but not to the ∨ or the →; and the third ¬ is subordinate to the second ¬, as well as to the ∧, but not to the ∨ or the →. If an order of precedence is adopted for the connectives, viz., with ¬ applying first, then ∧ and ∨, then →, and finally ↔, this formula may be written in the less parenthesized form , which some may find easier to read.
Quantifiers
The scope of a quantifier is the part of a logical expression over which the quantifier exerts control. It is the shortest full sentence written right after the quantifier, often in parentheses; some authors describe this as including the variable written right after the universal or existential quantifier. In the formula ∀xP, for example, P (or xP) is the scope of the quantifier ∀x (or ∀).
This gives rise to the following definitions:
- An occurrence of a quantifier or , immediately followed by an occurrence of the variable , as in or , is said to be -binding.
- An occurrence of a variable in a formula is free in if, and only if, it is not in the scope of any -binding quantifier in ; otherwise it is bound in .
- A closed formula is one in which no variable occurs free; a formula which is not closed is open.
- An occurrence of a quantifier or is vacuous if, and only if, its scope is or , and the variable does not occur free in .
- A variable is free for a variable if, and only if, no free occurrences of lie within the scope of a quantification on .
- A quantifier whose scope contains another quantifier is said to have wider scope than the second, which, in turn, is said to have narrower scope than the first.
See also
Notes
- These definitions follow the common practice of using Greek letters as metalogical symbols which may stand for symbols in a formal language for propositional or predicate logic. In particular, and are used to stand for any formulae whatsoever, whereas and are used to stand for propositional variables.
References
- ^ Bostock, David (1997). Intermediate logic. Oxford : New York: Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press. pp. 8, 79. ISBN 978-0-19-875141-0.
- ^ Cook, Roy T. (March 20, 2009). Dictionary of Philosophical Logic. Edinburgh University Press. pp. 99, 180, 254. ISBN 978-0-7486-3197-1.
- ^ Rich, Elaine; Cline, Alan Kaylor. Quantifier Scope.
- ^ Makridis, Odysseus (February 21, 2022). Symbolic Logic. Springer Nature. pp. 93–95. ISBN 978-3-030-67396-3.
- ^ "3.3.2: Quantifier Scope, Bound Variables, and Free Variables". Humanities LibreTexts. January 21, 2017. Retrieved June 10, 2024.
- ^ Lemmon, Edward John (1998). Beginning logic. Boca Raton, FL: Chapman & Hall/CRC. pp. 45–48. ISBN 978-0-412-38090-7.
- ^ Gillon, Brendan S. (March 12, 2019). Natural Language Semantics: Formation and Valuation. MIT Press. pp. 250–253. ISBN 978-0-262-03920-8.
- ^ "Examples | Logic Notes - ANU". users.cecs.anu.edu.au. Retrieved June 10, 2024.
- Suppes, Patrick; Hill, Shirley (April 30, 2012). First Course in Mathematical Logic. Courier Corporation. pp. 23–26. ISBN 978-0-486-15094-9.
- Kirk, Donna (March 22, 2023). "2.2. Compound Statements". Contemporary Mathematics. OpenStax.
- ^ Bell, John L.; Machover, Moshé (April 15, 2007). "Chapter 1. Beginning mathematical logic". A Course in Mathematical Logic. Elsevier Science Ltd. p. 17. ISBN 978-0-7204-2844-5.
- ^ Uzquiano, Gabriel (2022), "Quantifiers and Quantification", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved June 10, 2024
- Allen, Colin; Hand, Michael (2001). Logic primer (2nd ed.). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. p. 66. ISBN 978-0-262-51126-1.