Misplaced Pages

Scope (logic)

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
(Redirected from Scope of a quantification) Range of application for a quantifier or connective in a logical formula

In logic, the scope of a quantifier or connective is the shortest formula in which it occurs, determining the range in the formula to which the quantifier or connective is applied. The notions of a free variable and bound variable are defined in terms of whether that formula is within the scope of a quantifier, and the notions of a dominant connective and subordinate connective are defined in terms of whether a connective includes another within its scope.

Connectives

Logical connectives
NOT ¬ A , A , A ¯ , A {\displaystyle \neg A,-A,{\overline {A}},\sim A}
AND A B , A B , A B , A   &   B , A   & &   B {\displaystyle A\land B,A\cdot B,AB,A\ \&\ B,A\ \&\&\ B}
NAND A ¯ B , A B , A B , A B ¯ {\displaystyle A{\overline {\land }}B,A\uparrow B,A\mid B,{\overline {A\cdot B}}}
OR A B , A + B , A B , A B {\displaystyle A\lor B,A+B,A\mid B,A\parallel B}
NOR A ¯ B , A B , A + B ¯ {\displaystyle A{\overline {\lor }}B,A\downarrow B,{\overline {A+B}}}
XNOR A B , A ¯ B ¯ {\displaystyle A\odot B,{\overline {A{\overline {\lor }}B}}}
equivalent A B , A B , A B {\displaystyle A\equiv B,A\Leftrightarrow B,A\leftrightharpoons B}
XOR A _ B , A B {\displaystyle A{\underline {\lor }}B,A\oplus B}
└nonequivalent A B , A B , A B {\displaystyle A\not \equiv B,A\not \Leftrightarrow B,A\nleftrightarrow B}
implies A B , A B , A B {\displaystyle A\Rightarrow B,A\supset B,A\rightarrow B}
nonimplication (NIMPLY) A B , A B , A B {\displaystyle A\not \Rightarrow B,A\not \supset B,A\nrightarrow B}
converse A B , A B , A B {\displaystyle A\Leftarrow B,A\subset B,A\leftarrow B}
converse nonimplication A B , A B , A B {\displaystyle A\not \Leftarrow B,A\not \subset B,A\nleftarrow B}
Related concepts
Applications
Category

The scope of a logical connective occurring within a formula is the smallest well-formed formula that contains the connective in question. The connective with the largest scope in a formula is called its dominant connective, main connective, main operator, major connective, or principal connective; a connective within the scope of another connective is said to be subordinate to it.

For instance, in the formula ( ( ( P Q ) ¬ Q ) ( ¬ ¬ P Q ) ) {\displaystyle (\left(\left(P\rightarrow Q\right)\lor \lnot Q\right)\leftrightarrow \left(\lnot \lnot P\land Q\right))} , the dominant connective is ↔, and all other connectives are subordinate to it; the → is subordinate to the ∨, but not to the ∧; the first ¬ is also subordinate to the ∨, but not to the →; the second ¬ is subordinate to the ∧, but not to the ∨ or the →; and the third ¬ is subordinate to the second ¬, as well as to the ∧, but not to the ∨ or the →. If an order of precedence is adopted for the connectives, viz., with ¬ applying first, then ∧ and ∨, then →, and finally ↔, this formula may be written in the less parenthesized form ( P Q ) ¬ Q ¬ ¬ P Q {\displaystyle \left(P\rightarrow Q\right)\lor \lnot Q\leftrightarrow \lnot \lnot P\land Q} , which some may find easier to read.

Quantifiers

The scope of a quantifier is the part of a logical expression over which the quantifier exerts control. It is the shortest full sentence written right after the quantifier, often in parentheses; some authors describe this as including the variable written right after the universal or existential quantifier. In the formula ∀xP, for example, P (or xP) is the scope of the quantifier ∀x (or ∀).

This gives rise to the following definitions:

  • An occurrence of a quantifier {\displaystyle \forall } or {\displaystyle \exists } , immediately followed by an occurrence of the variable ξ {\displaystyle \xi } , as in ξ {\displaystyle \forall \xi } or ξ {\displaystyle \exists \xi } , is said to be ξ {\displaystyle \xi } -binding.
  • An occurrence of a variable ξ {\displaystyle \xi } in a formula ϕ {\displaystyle \phi } is free in ϕ {\displaystyle \phi } if, and only if, it is not in the scope of any ξ {\displaystyle \xi } -binding quantifier in ϕ {\displaystyle \phi } ; otherwise it is bound in ϕ {\displaystyle \phi } .
  • A closed formula is one in which no variable occurs free; a formula which is not closed is open.
  • An occurrence of a quantifier ξ {\displaystyle \forall \xi } or ξ {\displaystyle \exists \xi } is vacuous if, and only if, its scope is ξ ψ {\displaystyle \forall \xi \psi } or ξ ψ {\displaystyle \exists \xi \psi } , and the variable ξ {\displaystyle \xi } does not occur free in ψ {\displaystyle \psi } .
  • A variable ζ {\displaystyle \zeta } is free for a variable ξ {\displaystyle \xi } if, and only if, no free occurrences of ξ {\displaystyle \xi } lie within the scope of a quantification on ζ {\displaystyle \zeta } .
  • A quantifier whose scope contains another quantifier is said to have wider scope than the second, which, in turn, is said to have narrower scope than the first.

See also

Notes

  1. These definitions follow the common practice of using Greek letters as metalogical symbols which may stand for symbols in a formal language for propositional or predicate logic. In particular, ϕ {\displaystyle \phi } and ψ {\displaystyle \psi } are used to stand for any formulae whatsoever, whereas ξ {\displaystyle \xi } and ζ {\displaystyle \zeta } are used to stand for propositional variables.

References

  1. ^ Bostock, David (1997). Intermediate logic. Oxford : New York: Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press. pp. 8, 79. ISBN 978-0-19-875141-0.
  2. ^ Cook, Roy T. (March 20, 2009). Dictionary of Philosophical Logic. Edinburgh University Press. pp. 99, 180, 254. ISBN 978-0-7486-3197-1.
  3. ^ Rich, Elaine; Cline, Alan Kaylor. Quantifier Scope.
  4. ^ Makridis, Odysseus (February 21, 2022). Symbolic Logic. Springer Nature. pp. 93–95. ISBN 978-3-030-67396-3.
  5. ^ "3.3.2: Quantifier Scope, Bound Variables, and Free Variables". Humanities LibreTexts. January 21, 2017. Retrieved June 10, 2024.
  6. ^ Lemmon, Edward John (1998). Beginning logic. Boca Raton, FL: Chapman & Hall/CRC. pp. 45–48. ISBN 978-0-412-38090-7.
  7. ^ Gillon, Brendan S. (March 12, 2019). Natural Language Semantics: Formation and Valuation. MIT Press. pp. 250–253. ISBN 978-0-262-03920-8.
  8. ^ "Examples | Logic Notes - ANU". users.cecs.anu.edu.au. Retrieved June 10, 2024.
  9. Suppes, Patrick; Hill, Shirley (April 30, 2012). First Course in Mathematical Logic. Courier Corporation. pp. 23–26. ISBN 978-0-486-15094-9.
  10. Kirk, Donna (March 22, 2023). "2.2. Compound Statements". Contemporary Mathematics. OpenStax.
  11. ^ Bell, John L.; Machover, Moshé (April 15, 2007). "Chapter 1. Beginning mathematical logic". A Course in Mathematical Logic. Elsevier Science Ltd. p. 17. ISBN 978-0-7204-2844-5.
  12. ^ Uzquiano, Gabriel (2022), "Quantifiers and Quantification", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved June 10, 2024
  13. Allen, Colin; Hand, Michael (2001). Logic primer (2nd ed.). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. p. 66. ISBN 978-0-262-51126-1.
Categories:
Scope (logic) Add topic