Misplaced Pages

Democratic peace theory: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editNext edit →Content deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 02:07, 14 August 2005 edit208.20.251.27 (talk) Supportive← Previous edit Revision as of 18:35, 14 August 2005 edit undoUltramarine (talk | contribs)33,507 edits Numerous changes to longer versionNext edit →
Line 1: Line 1:
{{twoversions|19130671}} {{twoversions|19130671}}
{{npov}} {{npov}}
] was an early peace theorist, from the late 18th century.]] ] first posited an early theory of democratic peace in the late 18th century.]]
The '''democratic peace theory''' or simply '''democratic peace''' (often '''DPT''' and sometimes '''democratic pacifism''') is a ] in ] and ] which holds that ]—specifically, ]—never or almost never go to ] with one another. Despite criticism, the democratic peace theory has grown in prominence among political scientists in the last two decades and has become influential in the policy world in Western countries. ] remarked that the democratic peace is "the closest thing we have to a law in international politics." The '''democratic peace theory''' or simply '''democratic peace''' (often '''DPT''' and sometimes '''democratic pacifism''') is a ] in ] and ] which holds that ]—specifically, ]—never or almost never go to ] with one another. Despite criticism, the democratic peace theory has grown in prominence among political scientists in the last two decades and has become influential in the policy world in Western countries. Scholar ] famously remarked that the democratic peace is "the closest thing we have to a law in international politics."


==History of the theories== ==History of the theories==
===Early theories===
The idea that democracy is a source of world peace came relatively late in ]. No ancient author seems to have thought so. Early authors referred to ]s rather than democracies, since the word democracy had a bad name until early modern times. ] believed that republics were by nature excellent war-makers and empire-builders, citing ] as the prime example. Modern theories of democatic peace are a quite recent branch among the descendants of ]'s 1795 essay, ''Project for a Perpetual Peace''.
The idea that democracy is a source of world peace came relatively late in political theory.
No ancient author seems to have thought so. Early authors referred to republics rather than democracies, since the word democracy had acquired a bad name until early modern times. ] believed that republics were by nature excellent war-makers and empire-builders, citing Rome as the prime example. It was ] who first foreshadowed the theory in his essay "Perpetual Peace" written in 1795, although he thought that democracy was only of several necessary conditions for a perpetual peace. Since ], there has been widespread popular rhetoric that democratic states are peace-loving, but the idea was not systematically studied by social science. The gradual spread of liberal democracy in the world in the second half of the 20th century drew greater attention to the relationship between democracy and peace.


===Modern theories===
Kant's essay, however, differs radically from the modern theories. He speaks of republican (''republikanisch''), not democratic, states; which he defines to have ] and ]al governments. He does not discuss ], which is quite important to the modern theorists; his commentators dispute whether it is implied by his language. Most importantly, he does not regard ]an governments as sufficient by themselves to produce peace: Not only does he require a preliminary ] (including the abolition of ] and of the funding of warfare by state debt, and the repudiation of all claims to interfere with the constitution or government of another state) but republicanism is only one provision of three. He requires
*republicanism
*hospitality, the acknowledgement of the ] to freely move and resettle in another state.
*and a ].
On the other hand, he does not claim that republics will be at peace only with each other, but regards them as more pacific in general.


In ], ], then a Wisconsin ], published a paper asserting that no two ] had ever been at war with each other. This was also claimed at greater length in ] by ], professor of ] at the ], and much of this research is available on his web-site. The term also refers to an ever-increasing state of ], which Rummel credits to democracy. The following propositions formed the basis of Rummel's original theory:
The general idea that popular and ]s would be more inclined to promote peace and commerce became one current in the stream of European thought and political practice. It was one element of the American policy of ] and the foreign policy of ]. It was also represented in the ] ] of ], ], and ], although other planks in Kant's platform had even more influence. In the next generation, Kant's program was represented by the ] and the ].


*Democracies do not make war on each other.
Kant's essay is a three-legged stool (besides the preliminary disarmament). Democratic peace theories variously hold that the first leg is sufficient by itself, or will produce the other two. In ], ] relied only upon the second leg, arguing that modern commerce made war necessarily unprofitable, even for the technically victorious country, and therefore the possibility of successful war was '']''. ] had described the ] as ] for the upper classes; ] argued that ] made modern ]s inherently peaceful and opposed to conquest and ], which economically favored the old ] elites.
*The more democratic two nations are, the less the violence between them.
*Democracies engage in the least amounts of foreign violence.
*Democracies display, by far, the least amounts of internal violence.
*Modern democracies have virtually no "]" (i.e. ] and ])
A related but slightly different concept is Rummel's Law, which states that the less freedom a people have, the more likely their rulers are to murder them.


As the theory took shape in the ], particularly through the work of ] and ], it increasingly focused on the "weak" proposition that democracies tend to behave peacefully towards each other. The "strong" proposition that democracies are in general more peaceful in world affairs drew less wide acceptance.
The third leg, the idea that a confederation of peaceable princes could produce a perpetual peace, is much older than Kant. ] attempted to actually create such a confederation. One was also proposed by ] and ]. Kant had distinguished his league from a universal state; ] proposed, in ''Union Now''(1938) , a union of the democratic states modelled after the Constitution of the United States. He foretold that trade and the peaceable ways of democracy would keep this Union perpetual, but counted on the combined power of the Union to deter the ] from war.


The theory reached an audience outside academia with President ]'s ], Jan 25, 1994 "Ultimately, the best strategy to ensure our security and to build a durable peace is to support the advance of democracy elsewhere. Democracies don't attack each other."
] proposed that disarmament, arbitration, and the renunciation of colonies would produce perpetual peace, thus relying merely on Kant's preliminary articles and on none of the three main points; contrary to the modern theorists, he relied on public opinion, even against the ]. Many have followed him since.


==Causes==
In ], ], then a Wisconsin ], published a paper asserting that no two democracies had ever been at war with each other, and substantially republished it in an industrial trade journal in ]. This was also claimed at greater length in ] by ], professor of ] at the ], and much of this research is available on his web-site.
Many theoretical arguments have been put forward as explanations for the democratic peace. Dating back to ], many have argued that democracies are characterized by the ], and are therefore inclined to resolve disputes between them through ].


Other scholars suggest a theory of common ]: the citizens of democratic societies are less likely to view the citizens of other democracies as enemies, and since their support for the war is necessary (due to the democratic system), war is less likely.
] was the first democratic peace theorist to observe the similarity to Kant, and published a largely accurate summary of Kant's essay. He, working with ], distinguished between the '''strong''' form of the theory (that democracies tend to be peaceful in general; and the '''weak''' form, that they tend to be peaceful with each other.) He also studied the even weaker proposition that liberal regimes have less purely internal conflict.


Following Rummel, some support the idea that democracies are inherently peaceful because wide citizen participation ensures that decision making power lies in the hands of those most likely to be killed or wounded in wars, and their relatives and friends. This last argument cannot explain why democracies are very bellicose towards non-democratic states while remaining peaceful towards each other, unless we also suppose that citizens of democratic states feel constantly threatened by the existence of non-democracies or otherwise are provoked by them. The argument that democratic peace arises from citizens avoiding casualties is strengthened by democracies seeming less reluctant to start low-conflict conflicts. This idea also suggests that the relationship in the DPT became stronger when graphic movies and television made wars less romantic.
==Democratic peace theories==


See also the "Causation is not correlation" section below for a discussion of the hypothesis that it is not democracy itself but some other factor(s) associated with democratic states that explain the peace.
A democratic peace theory has to define what it means by "democracy" and what it means by "peace" (or, more often, "war"), and what it claims as the link between the two.


==Statistical studies supporting the DPT==
===Democracy===
Babst (1972) concluded that no wars had been fought between democracies between 1789 and 1941. Singer (1976) supported this. Doyle (1983) found that "constitutionally secure liberal states have yet to engage in wars with one another".
Democratic peace theorists have used different terms for the class of states they consider peaceable; Babst called them ], Rummell ], Doyle ]s. In general, these require not only that the government and legislature be chosen by free and genuinely contested elections, but more besides


Rummel studied all wars between 1816 and 1991 and found 198 wars between non-democracies, 155 wars between democracies and non-democracies, and 0 wars between democracies . He argues that this is strongly statistically significant. For example, during the 1946-1986 period there were 45 states that had a democratic regime; 109 that did not. There were thus 6,876 state dyads (e.g., Bolivia-Chile), of which 990 were democratic-democratic dyads. None of the 990 fought each other. Using the binomial theorem, the probability of the 990 dyads not engaging in war is .9953 to the 990th power or .0099, which rounded off, equals .01. The probability of this lack of war between democracies being by chance is virtually 100 to 1.
There are several lists of democracies. ] drew up a list of government types by country and year, the ]. This is a ranking on two ten-point scales, one for the degree of democracy, one for the degree of ]; but he calls the countries which score above 6 on the first scale simply '''the''' democracies; and those which score above 5 on the second, the autocracies. Gurr calls States which do neither ]; no state has yet done both. Many theorists simply use the binary version of Gurr's list: democracy/no democracy.


Maoz & Abdolai (1989) analyzed all wars between 1816 and 1976 and found no wars between democracies and that this is statistically significant. They also found less lower-level conflicts between democracies. Breemer (1992) reported similar findings for the years between 1816 and 1965. Ray (1993, 1995) found no wars between democracies.
Dean Babst made his own decisions on what was a democracy. He required also a ], asserting (wrongly) that this existed in the United States back to 1789 and in Britain back to the 1830's.


Several different kinds of statistical analyses find support for the DPT, including such techniques as logistic regression, poisson regression, and negative binomial analyses (King 1989). Studies using the Polity Data Set have concluded that the theory is also validated when a continuous measure of democracy is used (i.e. the higher two countries' joint scores, the lower their chance of being involved in a war against each other). Recently, also statistical analyses using ]s find support for theory, both during and before the Cold War .
More recent theorists have set a numerical limit on suffrage, say, that half or two-thirds of the male population be able to vote. Rummel, for example, also requires that the democracy be '''stabilized''', which he defines as having existed for three years.


Democracies do sometimes initiate wars against authoritarian states. Some argue that democracies usually enter these wars because they are provoked by authoritarian states. Several papers shows that democracies are slightly, but significantly less involved in wars in general than others states, and that they also initiate wars less frequently than non-democratic states .
===War===


Some statistical research indicates that enduring rivalries of all types are rare among democratic dyads. This pacifying effect of democracy appears to strengthen over time after the transition to joint democracy, which is consistent with the onset and deepening of democratic norms. Rivalries show a decreasing propensity for militarized conflict within a year of the transition to joint democracy, and this propensity decreases almost to zero within five years .
Many theorists have used the convenient list at the ] at the ], which compiled the wars from 1816 to 1991 with at least a thousand battlefield casualties. This data is particularly convenient for statistical analysis, and the large-scale statistical studies cited below have used this definition.


A recent theory is that democracies can be divided into "pacifist" and "militant". While both avoid attacking democracies, "militant" democracies have tendency to deep distrust and confrontational policies against dictatorships and may initiate wars against them. Most wars by democracies since 1950 have involved only four nations: the U.S., the U.K., Israel, and India .
===Claims===
Democratic peace theorists make two possible connections between democracy and war:
*Some claim that democracies, properly defined, have ''never'' made war on each other; these face the difficulty that Ted Gurr classes both ] and the ] as democracies in ], the year of the ].
*Others claim that two democracies are ''less likely'' to make war on each other than other pairs of states.


The historical definition of democracy has shifted over time, as ] and political ]s have been expanded to greater segments of the population. Continuous measures of democracy used in statistical studies attempt to create a consistent scale of comparison for all states. Most statistical work on the democratic peace has focused on the 19th and 20th centuries, but there is a significant body of literature on the applicability of the theory outside the modern western world.
While the following claims are not strictly part of the theory, they have been made by various democratic peace theorists and form an important part of the analysis of causes.


==The methodology of the studies==
*The more democratic two nations are, the less the violence between them. (This may include violence short of full-scale war, or may be a claim that such wars as do occur between democracies are waged with restraint.)
The studies supporting the DPT have often defined
*Democracies engage in the least amounts of foreign violence.
*'''war''' as any military action with more than 1000 killed in battle . This is the definition used in the authoritative ] at the University of Michigan. It counts 2000 cases of armed wars or other conflicts after 1816. The project has also supplied the data regarding wars for many of the studies.
*Democracies use less violence in their ''internal'' affairs. In particular, modern democracies do not murder their citizens.
*'''democracy''' as a stabilized ].
**Dean Babst made his own decisions on what was a democracy. He required also a ], asserting (wrongly) that this existed in the United States back to 1789 and in Britain back to the 1830's.
**The ] is put together by a number of scholars, most prominent among whom is ]. They apply an 11-point ] scale of democracy to almost every state in the world for every year from 1800 to the 1990s. Those democracy scores are themselves sums of scores on various dimensions reflecting, for example, the selection of government executives by election, the openness of executive recruitment, and the parity between the executive and legislative branches of government.
**Rummel requires democracies to pass certain absolute criteria like voting rights for at least 2/3 of all adult males and being older than 3 years at the start of the war. He also has some implicit criteria; for example, the chief officer of the democracy must have had a contested ].
**Others have instead required that at least 50% of the adult population is allowed to vote, and that the political system in question has produced at least one peaceful, constitutional transfer of executive power from one independent political party to another by means of an election.


==Causes== ==Criticisms==
There are four logically distinguishable classes of criticism of any DPT:
"]," is a bedrock standard of ]. In order to bridge the gap from a statistical curiosity to a meaningful theory, the researcher must first identify a mechanism, and (ideally) make ] predictions based on that mechanism. Various suggestions have been made for the causes of the democratic peace. These do not, in general, depend on which version of the theory is being asserted. Most, if not all, such explanations focus on the fact that the consent of the citizenry is necessary for a democracy to initiate and sustain a war. Even where ] allow the executive to act without legislative approval, public acceptance, at the least, is needed to avoid an electoral backlash.
*That its creator was not '''accurate''' in applying his criteria to the historical record. (See Specific historic examples below).
*That the criteria are not '''appropriate''' in discussing the record. Critics may prefer that 'democracy' should exclude or include both of Germany and England during WWI, rather than separate them into democratic and non-democratic.
*That the peace theory does not actually '''mean''' very much. For example, that it applies to few states (very few before the twentieth century), and doesn't actually limit their behavior to each other very much. Any reasonable border which excludes WWI Germany may also excludes almost all states before the Cold War.
*That such peace as there has been between democracies is at least in part due to '''external causes'''. (See Correlation is not causation below).


These tend to overlap, being in fact complementary criticisms, and many critics make more than one of them. It is particularly hard to tell the first two classes apart on 1914 Germany, since DPTs must reject it on qualitative, not numerical, grounds.
Kant made the straightforward point that, since an absolute prince can order war "without the least sacrifice of the pleasures of his table, the chase, his country houses, his court functions, and the like", he will be likely to do so for light or trivial causes that the citizenry would never find sufficient. This, however, would explain why democracies prefer peace with all states, not just with each other. The wars of democracies with non-democracies must therefore be explained by other motives, such as provocations from reckless non-democratic states, or a belief that the two systems cannot peacefully co-exist.


==Specific historic examples==
Other scholars suggest a theory of common ]: the citizens of democratic societies tend not to view the citizens of other democracies as enemies, and wars against other democracies are unlikely to get the necessary support. This resembles Kant's article of "hospitality", as do the economic arguments of Angell and Schumpeter.
===Liberal democracy===
For the First World War critics have argued that supporters of the DPT are mistaken, either in denying that Germany was a democracy (the ] was elected by universal male suffrage, its votes of no confidence did cause governments to fall, and it did vote on whether to fund the war - which passed overwhelmingly) or that the supporter are wrong in affirming Britain to be one (the 1911 elections enfranchised only 60% of the British electorate, to say nothing of the Empire beyond the Seas, the majority of which had no say in the decision at all). Supporters respond that at the time of World War I the German ] still had much power, he had direct control over the army, appointed and could dismiss the chancellor, and played a key role in foreign affairs. In effect, therefore, in foreign and military affairs, there was little democratic control. They also note that the Kaiser was also the King in the very large state of ] which had much influence over national politics, that Prussian government was not responsible to the Prussian Landtag (lower chamber), that the Landstag members were elected by a suffrage system based on tax-paying ability favoring the rich, and that the landed aristocracy of the ]s dominated all the higher civil offices and officer corps of the Army and Navy . If Britain was not a liberal democracy, then this is another reason why WWI was not a war between democracies.


There can be similar responses to other objections. During the ], only a small minority had the right to vote in the ], many new urban areas had no representation, the ballot was not secret, many seats in ] were appointed or openly bought from the owners of ]s, and the ] could ] all laws. The defenders of DPT exclude the ] because, in addition to it being an internal conflict, in the ], only 30-40% of male population could vote and there was never a competitive presidential election. Similarly, only a minority had the right to vote in the Boer states. <!--Hence the importance of the Transvaal War --> ], the president of ] at the time of the ], used terror tactics to silence critical press and the previously independent judiciary, for example storming the ] in order to force the Chief Justice out of office. ], the president of the Palestinian Authority at the start of the latest conflicts with ], can be criticized on similar grounds. There was never a democratic election in the ] before the ]. All the Mexican presidents at the time of the conflicts with the U.S., like ], took their power in ]s. The nations in the ] were ruled by ]s or had suffrage requirements like literacy or property that excluded a large part of the populations.
A recent paper by Mousseau suggests that the democratic peace is real, and results from economic causes, but that these effects only apply to relatively wealthy countries. This conclusion is consistent with earlier theories as well: the destruction caused by war should be less daunting to those with nothing to lose.


===Liberal democracies before the late nineteenth century?===
Rummel all of these as superficial. ] and ] propose that democracy involves a pervasive social mechanism (called a ''"social field"'') in which, "The primary mode of power is exchange, political system is democratic, and democratic government is but one of many groups and pyramids of power." In contrast, authoritarian systems involve a ''"social anti-field"'', " divides its members into those who command and those who must obey, thus creating a schism separating all members and dividing all issues, a latent conflict front along which violence can break out." Thus, the citizens of a democracy are habituated to compromise, conflict resolution, and to viewing unfavorable outcomes as temporary and/or tolerable.


Whether the pre-modern states that once identified themselves as democracies fulfill modern criteria remains controversial. In Ancient Greece, such city-states did fight wars between each other (most noted is the Athenian expedition against ] during the ]). Many do not deem Ancient Greek city-states as sufficiently democratic because of the large numbers of slaves and other non-voting inhabitants. It is estimated that only 16% of the population in Athens had the right to vote. There were also three great wars between ] and ]; and the ] sacked ]. Similar questions arise about the persistent wars among ], ], ], and other ] ]s. These states were also not as democratic as modern democracies, but at least as much as Athens and more so than Syracuse.
==Statistical studies supporting the DPT==
Babst (1972) concluded that no wars had been fought between democracies between 1789 and 1941. Singer (1976) supported this. Doyle (1983) found that "constitutionally secure liberal states have yet to engage in wars with one another".


An interesting case is the ], which had some qualities of today's democracies and in which ] (the nobles), using ] (a parliament), blocked many ] attempts to declare a war on other countries. Some scholars have put forward the ] (or parts of it) and the Six ] Nations as early examples of communities of democratic states upholding the theory.
Rummel studied all wars between 1816 and 1991 and found 198 wars between non-democracies, 155 wars between democracies and non-democracies, and 0 wars between democracies. Maoz & Abdolai (1989) analyzed all wars between 1816 and 1976 and found no wars between democracies and that this is statistically significant. They also found less lower-level conflicts between democracies. Breemer (1992) reported similar findings for the years between 1816 and 1965. Ray (1993, 1995) found no wars between democracies.


===Deaths in battle===
Democracies do sometimes initiate wars against authoritarian states. Some argue that democracies usually enter these wars because they are provoked by authoritarian states. Several papers show that democracies are slightly, but significantly less involved in wars in general than others states, and that they also initiate wars less frequently than non-democratic states .
The rule of at least 1000 killed in battle excludes attacks by one democracy on another in such overwhelming force that there is no effective resistance, and thus few deaths in battle (some ] and small scale foreign interventions by the United States may be examples.)


Democracies have engaged in covert conflict resulting in a change of regime on the losing side. The British- and American-supported 1953 coup d'etat in ] against ] and the 1954 U.S.-backed coup in ], led by ] as examples of such events. The rule also excludes these events.
==Criticisms==
There are four logically distinguishable classes of criticism of any DPT:
*That its creator was not '''accurate''' in applying his criteria to the historical record.
*That the criteria are not '''appropriate''' in discussing the record.
*That the peace theory does not actually '''mean''' very much. For example, that it applies to few states (very few before the twentieth century), and doesn't actually limit their behavior to each other very much.
*That such peace as there has been between democracies is at least in part due to '''external causes'''.


There is at least one democracy which formally declared war on another when the United Kingdom declared war on ] on ], ] in reaction to the ], when Finland allied with ] in attacking the ]. However, the United Kingdom's only significant act of war happened prior to the declaration (a ] raid on the port of ] on ], ]). However, Finland spent World War II fighting a totalitarian opponent who had attacked the nation, the United Kingdom and Finland for almost the whole of ] carefully avoided attacking each other, and the casualties in the conflict with the United Kingdom were too few to be classified as a war statistically. The lavish material support the United Kingdom and the United States provided to Soviet Union raises the question if democracies can make war against other democracies through ].
For example, the ] is a difficult case for all DPT's, which deal with it by deciding that the ] were not democracies on the grounds that the ] had the power to appoint his ministers, that he and the General Staff made the decision for war, as did ] in ], and that many structural features of the ] made democratic institutions ineffective. The status of ] raises very complex questions of how much power the ] had by 1914, and how much the ]s were answerable to the ] they had called.


===Rummel's time limit===
The first class of critics argue that DPT is mistaken, either in denying that Germany was a democracy (the ] was elected by universal suffrage, its votes of no confidence did cause governments to fall, and it did vote on whether to fund the war - which passed overwhelmingly), or in claiming it to be less democratic than Britain (the 1911 elections enfranchised only 60% of the British male population, to say nothing of the Empire beyond the Seas, the majority of which had no say in the decision at all).
Rummel's version of the DOT has a requirement that the democratic states must be older than three years excludes the war between the ] and the ]. The ] is excluded if one considers the ] to have become democratic after the first election in November ] or when the constitution was amended so that the parliament could control the cabinet in April ]. The war started in October ], which would be before four years had passed. Critics instead argue that democracy occurred in July 1908 when a constitution was introduced. It is also doubtful if the opposing Christian states fulfill the democratic criteria since the Kings continued to have extensive powers in all of them.


The time limit and and other requirements like democratic institutions and elections on both sides, also exclude ]s within democracies over legitimacy or secession, such as the ], the ] war, the ] and the ] which followed, and the ] civil wars in ], ], ] and ].
Whether or not it is possible to thread a line between Germany and England, the second class prefers a border of 'democracy' that lies in the interval between both Germany and England, on the one end, and perfect democracy on the other; or between both of them and totalitarianism. (The DPT theorist Rummel has said that the word 'democracy' was not important to his argument; but his use of it has made his claim far more interesting.) The third class of critics observe that any reasonable border which excludes Wilhelmine Germany also excludes almost all states before the Cold War. The fourth class explains the Cold War democratic peace as a special case.


==Correlation is not causation==
These tend to overlap, being in fact complementary criticisms, and many critics make more than one of them. It is particularly hard to tell the first two classes apart on 1914 Germany, since DPTs must reject it on qualitative, not numerical, grounds.
A statistical ] does not establish ]. Critics have thus argued that the peace may be explained by other factors in democratic states that are not related to democracy. Supporters of the DPT argue that many studies have controlled for such factors and that the DPT is still validated. For example, Bremer (1992, 1993) controlled for contiguity, power status, alliance ties, militarization, economic development, and power ratios. Maoz & Russett (1992, 1993) and Russett (1993) controlled for contiguity, alliance ties, economic wealth and growth, political stability, and power ratios.


===External causes=== ===Trade===
Following Schumpeter, some hypothesize that the phenomenon is explained by the fact that democratic countries tend to be capitalist states, whose ] relations with one another create ] among them. This interdependence constrains the ability and willingness of democratic nations to go to war with each other due to the incurred costs in lost trade. However, one problem with this interpretation is the existence of non-democratic capitalist states, who often have made war with each other or with democratic states. However, a recent study shows that economically important trade has a substantively important pacifying effect which is independent of democracy. It also shows that democracy does have a pacifying effect independent of trade. This study also indicates that the DPT is not a significant factor unless both of the democracies have a GDP/capita of at least 1400 USD. Economic development below this may hinder the development of liberal institutions. .
In addition to the external cause of the ], the democratic peace has been attributed to wealth, as above, and to geographic isolation. How likely was nineteenth-century ] to go to war with the United States? Or (in the Cold War ]) ] with ]?


===Geographic isolation===
Some democratic peace theorists have controlled for these variables. Bremer (1992, 1993) controlled for contiguity, power status, alliance ties, militarization, economic development, and power ratios. Maoz & Russett (1992, 1993) and Russett (1993) controlled for contiguity, alliance ties, economic wealth and growth, political stability, and power ratios. They also studied the period from 1945 and 1986 and discounted all pairs that did not involve a major power or nations that were not geographically continuous. .
Some critics have argued that few democracies mean that they are geographically isolated and thus unable to make war with each other. However, Maoz & Russet studied the period from 1945 and 1986 and discounted all dyads that did not involve a major power or nations that were not geographically continuous. The DPT was still validated. Bremer (1992) and other studies also support this conclusion. Glieditsch (1995) demonstrated that democratic dyads have not been more separated than non-democratic dyads. Supporters also note that today more than 50% of all nations are democratic .


===The Cold War peace=== ===The bloc peace theory===
The chief external cause, cited (with many other criticisms) in Joanne Gowa's ''Ballots and Bullets: The Elusive Democratic Peace'', is that the structure of the international political system during the ] was responsible for creating the illusion of a democratic peace. At about the same time many of today's democracies came into existence, the ] divided much of the world into two systems of permanent institutionalized alliances. (Many states belonged to neither; chief among these was the ] after ].) ] argues in ''Ballots and Bullets: The Elusive Democratic Peace'', that the structure of the international political system during the ] was responsible for creating the illusion of a democratic peace. At about the same time many of today's democracies came into existence, the ] divided much of the world into two systems of institutionalized alliances. (Many states belonged to neither; chief among these was the People's Republic of China after 1961.) These critics claim the inter-democratic peace of the period is explained by a larger "bloc peace theory": they ascribe the inter-democratic peace of the period to this structure of blocs: almost all the democracies of the Cold War were members of the Western bloc, and the members of that bloc abstained from attacking one another in a collective effort to contain the bigger threat posed by Communism. Not only was the system of alliances produced by this common interest; also, once it had come into existence, the relations between two members of the bloc were not permitted to decline into full-scale war; the alliance provided their common allies with the interest and the leverage to prevent it.


Supporters of the DPT note that Bremer (1992), Maoz & Russett (1992, 1993), Russett (1993), Oneal et al (1996), Barbieri (1996a), Oneal & Russett (1997), and Oneal & Ray (1997) all have controlled for alliance ties in their statistical studies supporting the DPT, contradicting Gowa's theory.
These critics ascribe the inter-democratic peace of the period to this structure of blocs: almost all the democracies of the Cold War were members of the Western bloc, and the members of that bloc abstained from attacking one another in a collective effort to contain the bigger threat posed by Communism.


====Specific historic examples====
Not only was the system of alliances produced by this common interest; also, once it had come into existence, the relations between two members of the bloc were not permitted to decline into full-scale war; the alliance provided their common allies with the interest and the leverage to prevent it.


====During the Cold War====
There have been wars between members of other alliances, although one study finds that 88% of the treaties made in the last two centuries have been kept. This line of criticism need not claim that alliances prevent ''all'' wars; just that the ] alliance, and the common interest it represented, caused enough peace that the rest may be the result of other causes or of chance.


The bloc peace theory makes, in some ways, broader claims than DPT. For example, some skeptics of DPT argue that the ] was suppressed in less than two weeks since Egypt was a marginal member of the Western bloc. This as confirmation that potential attacks on full members would have been stopped before they began. Even though Egypt was not a democracy, the ] treaties were supposed to bind her closely to Britain. However, it is doubtful that Egypt was an Western ally at all because Egypt had nationalized the canal, the US had stopped foreign aid, and Egypt had bought weapons from the Communist states.
===Before the Cold War===


The DPT supporters have argued that while Gowa only applied the theory that external threats stopped internal wars to the democratic Western nations, such a theory also predicts that there should have been no wars at all in the Western bloc, including no wars involving dictatorships, and no wars in the opposing Communist bloc .
Before the Cold War, the limited period during which there was more than one non-allied democratic ] includes several crises between them, including the ] of ] and the ] crisis between the ] and ]; and the ] crisis between the ] and the ]. These were conducted as fiercely as many diplomatic conflicts involving a non-democratic state; and war was popular on both sides.


There were several wars between Communist nations: the ], the ], and the ]. However, Ethiopia and Somalia belonged to different blocs, even if both claimed to be socialist. There were also minor conflicts, not meeting the threshold of deaths, particularly the ] and the ]. Another possible counter example is the ]. However, many hold that (despite the Stalinist record of its chief) it was effectively a non-Communist regime and may have ceased to be part of the ] bloc, becoming either a neutral or a Western power. However, Nagy was a Communist, had been an agent for the Soviet security apparatus earlier, and was installed by the ].
==DPT and International Policy==


Supporters of the DPT also argue that the critics thus seem to define "bloc" arbitrarily in order to avoid some exceptions for the Communist states, arguing that the Western world similarly had many different "blocs" but without having wars between democracies. For instance, ] was antagonistic with the ] and expelled the NATO headquarters and all NATO forces from its territory; France, however, did not withdrew formally from NATO, and retained or even increased its ties to the other nations in the European Union. Supporters also note that the neutral democratic Western nations Sweden, Ireland, Austria, and Schwitzerland were not involved in wars with other democratic nations. If all capitalist democracies were to be considered part of a common bloc, then it may also be argued that China was still part of a common Communist bloc, and thus that the ] is another counter example to the bloc peace theory.
"Ultimately, the best strategy to ensure our security and to build a durable peace is to support the advance of democracy elsewhere. Democracies don't attack each other." William Clinton's 1994 , Jan 25, 1994


There were many large scale wars involving dictatorships and the absence of wars between democracies in the ] during the same period, which supports the DPT. However, there were few democracies there and then. On the other hand,many of the Western nations had or could easily develop the military capability to attack democracies in the Third World but did not.
"And the reason why I'm so strong on democracy is democracies don't go to war with each other. And the reason why is the people of most societies don't like war, and they understand what war means.... I've got great faith in democracies to promote peace. And that's why I'm such a strong believer that the way forward in the Middle East, the broader Middle East, is to promote democracy." George W. Bush at the , 12 November 2004.


There were wars in the Western bloc between democracies and dictatorships, arguably disproving the bloc peace theory. One example is the Turkish invasion of ] in ], at a time when Cyprus had British military bases and close ties to Turkey's NATO partner Greece. Another is the ]. However, the U.S. put pressure on the combatants to stop the Football War which fits the bloc peace theory. A third is the 1965 U.S. invasion of the ]. The ] and the ] may also be wars within the Western bloc, because Iraq belonged to ] and Israel received extensive aid from the U.S. Bloc peace theory supporters claim that CENTO was not a functioning organization and note that The Soviet-Iraqi Treaty of Friendship was signed in 1972. Still another examples are the two ]s, in which Arabic nations fought each other despite belonging to the ] and ]. All of these wars had more than 1000 military casualties . The ] almost qualify (936 causalities).
== References ==
Most of the following are from Rummel's extensive :


====Before the Cold War====

Critics of the DPT argue that before the Cold War, the limited period during which there was more than one non-allied democratic ] includes several crises between them, including the ] crisis, between the ] and ], and the ] crisis between the ] and the ]. These were conducted as fiercely as many diplomatic conflicts involving a non-democratic state; and war was popular on both sides.

On the other hand, even when there were conflicts, democracies did not make war with each other. Also, in the nineteenth century, much of the world was divided into blocs by the imperialist powers. This was often strictly regulated as when England and Russia divided Persia into two spheres of influence. Numerous wars occurred in these blocs, arguably contradicting the bloc peace theory, both by the imperialist powers when they extended direct rule and also between minor states in these blocs. For example, an incomplete list of wars in India after England had become the dominant European power includes three ], four ], two ]s, three ], the ], the ], and three ].

There were numerous wars in Latin America, despite belonging to an U.S. dominated bloc after the ]. This bloc was frequently threatened by the other imperialist blocs and sometimes direct military action occurred, like the French military invasion of Mexico. Examples of large scale wars in Latin America in this period include the ], the ], the ], the ], and the ]. There werr also several betrayls of formal treaties within blocs during WWII. Examples include the wars of Finland, Italy, Bulgaria, Roumania, and Hungary on their German ally in WWII and the German invasion of the Soviet Union despite the ] and its secret extensions.

====After the Cold War====

Supporters also argue that external causes cannot explain the continued peace between democracies after the end of the Cold War. Critics respond that the ] contains some of those democracies capable of maintaining a major war, and is also an institutionalized alliance. However, even those European states still have separate militaries and to a large degree separate foreign policy. There are also many democracies outside Europe .

== References ==
*Beck, Nathaniel, and Richard Tucker. Midwest Political Science Association: April 1998. *Beck, Nathaniel, and Richard Tucker. Midwest Political Science Association: April 1998.
* *
Line 122: Line 144:
*Lipson, Charles. ''Reliable Partners: How Democracies Have Made a Separate Peace''. Princeton University Press: 2003. ISBN 0691113904. *Lipson, Charles. ''Reliable Partners: How Democracies Have Made a Separate Peace''. Princeton University Press: 2003. ISBN 0691113904.
* *
*Plourde, Shawn May, 2004
*Ray, James Lee. ''Democracy and International Conflict: An Evaluation of the Democratic Peace Proposition''. University of South Carolina Press: 1998. ISBN 1570032416. *Ray, James Lee. ''Democracy and International Conflict: An Evaluation of the Democratic Peace Proposition''. University of South Carolina Press: 1998. ISBN 1570032416.
*Ray, James Lee. ''Annual Review of Political Science'' 1998:1, 27-46 *Ray, James Lee. ''Annual Review of Political Science'' 1998:1, 27-46
*Rummel, R.J. ''Power Kills: Democracy As a Method of Nonviolence''. Transaction Publishers: 2003. ISBN 0765805235. *Rummel, R.J. ''Power Kills: Democracy As a Method of Nonviolence''. Transaction Publishers: 2003. ISBN 0765805235.
*Rummel, R.J.
*Russett, Bruce. ''Grasping the Democratic Peace''. Princeton University Press: 1994. ISBN 0691001642. *Russett, Bruce. ''Grasping the Democratic Peace''. Princeton University Press: 1994. ISBN 0691001642.
*Schwartz, Thomas, and Kiron Skinner. ''The Wall Street Journal''. January 7, 1999.


==External links== ==External links==
===Supportive=== ===Supportive===
* *
*
*
*
**.


===Critical=== ===Critical===
* *
* *

]
]
]


==See also== ==See also==
Line 147: Line 164:
*] *]
*] *]

]
]
]


] ]

Revision as of 18:35, 14 August 2005

Accuracy disputeThis article appears to contradict the article 19130671. Please discuss at the talk page and do not remove this message until the contradictions are resolved.
The neutrality of this article is disputed. Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page. Please do not remove this message until conditions to do so are met. (Learn how and when to remove this message)
Famous philosopher Immanuel Kant first posited an early theory of democratic peace in the late 18th century.

The democratic peace theory or simply democratic peace (often DPT and sometimes democratic pacifism) is a theory in political science and philosophy which holds that democracies—specifically, liberal democracies—never or almost never go to war with one another. Despite criticism, the democratic peace theory has grown in prominence among political scientists in the last two decades and has become influential in the policy world in Western countries. Scholar Jack Levy famously remarked that the democratic peace is "the closest thing we have to a law in international politics."

History of the theories

Early theories

The idea that democracy is a source of world peace came relatively late in political theory. No ancient author seems to have thought so. Early authors referred to republics rather than democracies, since the word democracy had acquired a bad name until early modern times. Nicolo Machiavelli believed that republics were by nature excellent war-makers and empire-builders, citing Rome as the prime example. It was Immanuel Kant who first foreshadowed the theory in his essay "Perpetual Peace" written in 1795, although he thought that democracy was only of several necessary conditions for a perpetual peace. Since World War I, there has been widespread popular rhetoric that democratic states are peace-loving, but the idea was not systematically studied by social science. The gradual spread of liberal democracy in the world in the second half of the 20th century drew greater attention to the relationship between democracy and peace.

Modern theories

In 1964, Dean Babst, then a Wisconsin criminologist, published a paper asserting that no two liberal democracies had ever been at war with each other. This was also claimed at greater length in 1979 by R.J. Rummel, professor of Political Science at the University of Hawaii, and much of this research is available on his web-site. The term also refers to an ever-increasing state of world peace, which Rummel credits to democracy. The following propositions formed the basis of Rummel's original theory:

  • Democracies do not make war on each other.
  • The more democratic two nations are, the less the violence between them.
  • Democracies engage in the least amounts of foreign violence.
  • Democracies display, by far, the least amounts of internal violence.
  • Modern democracies have virtually no "democide" (i.e. genocide and mass murder)

A related but slightly different concept is Rummel's Law, which states that the less freedom a people have, the more likely their rulers are to murder them.

As the theory took shape in the 1980s, particularly through the work of Michael Doyle and Bruce Russett, it increasingly focused on the "weak" proposition that democracies tend to behave peacefully towards each other. The "strong" proposition that democracies are in general more peaceful in world affairs drew less wide acceptance.

The theory reached an audience outside academia with President Bill Clinton's State of the Union Address, Jan 25, 1994 "Ultimately, the best strategy to ensure our security and to build a durable peace is to support the advance of democracy elsewhere. Democracies don't attack each other."

Causes

Many theoretical arguments have been put forward as explanations for the democratic peace. Dating back to Immanuel Kant, many have argued that democracies are characterized by the rule of law, and are therefore inclined to resolve disputes between them through arbitration.

Other scholars suggest a theory of common culture: the citizens of democratic societies are less likely to view the citizens of other democracies as enemies, and since their support for the war is necessary (due to the democratic system), war is less likely.

Following Rummel, some support the idea that democracies are inherently peaceful because wide citizen participation ensures that decision making power lies in the hands of those most likely to be killed or wounded in wars, and their relatives and friends. This last argument cannot explain why democracies are very bellicose towards non-democratic states while remaining peaceful towards each other, unless we also suppose that citizens of democratic states feel constantly threatened by the existence of non-democracies or otherwise are provoked by them. The argument that democratic peace arises from citizens avoiding casualties is strengthened by democracies seeming less reluctant to start low-conflict conflicts. This idea also suggests that the relationship in the DPT became stronger when graphic movies and television made wars less romantic.

See also the "Causation is not correlation" section below for a discussion of the hypothesis that it is not democracy itself but some other factor(s) associated with democratic states that explain the peace.

Statistical studies supporting the DPT

Babst (1972) concluded that no wars had been fought between democracies between 1789 and 1941. Singer (1976) supported this. Doyle (1983) found that "constitutionally secure liberal states have yet to engage in wars with one another".

Rummel studied all wars between 1816 and 1991 and found 198 wars between non-democracies, 155 wars between democracies and non-democracies, and 0 wars between democracies . He argues that this is strongly statistically significant. For example, during the 1946-1986 period there were 45 states that had a democratic regime; 109 that did not. There were thus 6,876 state dyads (e.g., Bolivia-Chile), of which 990 were democratic-democratic dyads. None of the 990 fought each other. Using the binomial theorem, the probability of the 990 dyads not engaging in war is .9953 to the 990th power or .0099, which rounded off, equals .01. The probability of this lack of war between democracies being by chance is virtually 100 to 1.

Maoz & Abdolai (1989) analyzed all wars between 1816 and 1976 and found no wars between democracies and that this is statistically significant. They also found less lower-level conflicts between democracies. Breemer (1992) reported similar findings for the years between 1816 and 1965. Ray (1993, 1995) found no wars between democracies.

Several different kinds of statistical analyses find support for the DPT, including such techniques as logistic regression, poisson regression, and negative binomial analyses (King 1989). Studies using the Polity Data Set have concluded that the theory is also validated when a continuous measure of democracy is used (i.e. the higher two countries' joint scores, the lower their chance of being involved in a war against each other). Recently, also statistical analyses using neural nets find support for theory, both during and before the Cold War .

Democracies do sometimes initiate wars against authoritarian states. Some argue that democracies usually enter these wars because they are provoked by authoritarian states. Several papers shows that democracies are slightly, but significantly less involved in wars in general than others states, and that they also initiate wars less frequently than non-democratic states .

Some statistical research indicates that enduring rivalries of all types are rare among democratic dyads. This pacifying effect of democracy appears to strengthen over time after the transition to joint democracy, which is consistent with the onset and deepening of democratic norms. Rivalries show a decreasing propensity for militarized conflict within a year of the transition to joint democracy, and this propensity decreases almost to zero within five years .

A recent theory is that democracies can be divided into "pacifist" and "militant". While both avoid attacking democracies, "militant" democracies have tendency to deep distrust and confrontational policies against dictatorships and may initiate wars against them. Most wars by democracies since 1950 have involved only four nations: the U.S., the U.K., Israel, and India .

The historical definition of democracy has shifted over time, as civil and political rights have been expanded to greater segments of the population. Continuous measures of democracy used in statistical studies attempt to create a consistent scale of comparison for all states. Most statistical work on the democratic peace has focused on the 19th and 20th centuries, but there is a significant body of literature on the applicability of the theory outside the modern western world.

The methodology of the studies

The studies supporting the DPT have often defined

  • war as any military action with more than 1000 killed in battle . This is the definition used in the authoritative Correlates of War Project at the University of Michigan. It counts 2000 cases of armed wars or other conflicts after 1816. The project has also supplied the data regarding wars for many of the studies.
  • democracy as a stabilized liberal democracy.
    • Dean Babst made his own decisions on what was a democracy. He required also a secret ballot, asserting (wrongly) that this existed in the United States back to 1789 and in Britain back to the 1830's.
    • The Polity Data Set is put together by a number of scholars, most prominent among whom is Ted Gurr. They apply an 11-point ordinal scale of democracy to almost every state in the world for every year from 1800 to the 1990s. Those democracy scores are themselves sums of scores on various dimensions reflecting, for example, the selection of government executives by election, the openness of executive recruitment, and the parity between the executive and legislative branches of government.
    • Rummel requires democracies to pass certain absolute criteria like voting rights for at least 2/3 of all adult males and being older than 3 years at the start of the war. He also has some implicit criteria; for example, the chief officer of the democracy must have had a contested election.
    • Others have instead required that at least 50% of the adult population is allowed to vote, and that the political system in question has produced at least one peaceful, constitutional transfer of executive power from one independent political party to another by means of an election.

Criticisms

There are four logically distinguishable classes of criticism of any DPT:

  • That its creator was not accurate in applying his criteria to the historical record. (See Specific historic examples below).
  • That the criteria are not appropriate in discussing the record. Critics may prefer that 'democracy' should exclude or include both of Germany and England during WWI, rather than separate them into democratic and non-democratic.
  • That the peace theory does not actually mean very much. For example, that it applies to few states (very few before the twentieth century), and doesn't actually limit their behavior to each other very much. Any reasonable border which excludes WWI Germany may also excludes almost all states before the Cold War.
  • That such peace as there has been between democracies is at least in part due to external causes. (See Correlation is not causation below).

These tend to overlap, being in fact complementary criticisms, and many critics make more than one of them. It is particularly hard to tell the first two classes apart on 1914 Germany, since DPTs must reject it on qualitative, not numerical, grounds.

Specific historic examples

Liberal democracy

For the First World War critics have argued that supporters of the DPT are mistaken, either in denying that Germany was a democracy (the Reichstag was elected by universal male suffrage, its votes of no confidence did cause governments to fall, and it did vote on whether to fund the war - which passed overwhelmingly) or that the supporter are wrong in affirming Britain to be one (the 1911 elections enfranchised only 60% of the British electorate, to say nothing of the Empire beyond the Seas, the majority of which had no say in the decision at all). Supporters respond that at the time of World War I the German Kaiser still had much power, he had direct control over the army, appointed and could dismiss the chancellor, and played a key role in foreign affairs. In effect, therefore, in foreign and military affairs, there was little democratic control. They also note that the Kaiser was also the King in the very large state of Prussia which had much influence over national politics, that Prussian government was not responsible to the Prussian Landtag (lower chamber), that the Landstag members were elected by a suffrage system based on tax-paying ability favoring the rich, and that the landed aristocracy of the junkers dominated all the higher civil offices and officer corps of the Army and Navy . If Britain was not a liberal democracy, then this is another reason why WWI was not a war between democracies.

There can be similar responses to other objections. During the War of 1812, only a small minority had the right to vote in the United Kingdom, many new urban areas had no representation, the ballot was not secret, many seats in Parliament were appointed or openly bought from the owners of rotten boroughs, and the House of Lords could veto all laws. The defenders of DPT exclude the American Civil War because, in addition to it being an internal conflict, in the Confederate States of America, only 30-40% of male population could vote and there was never a competitive presidential election. Similarly, only a minority had the right to vote in the Boer states. Nawaz Sharif, the president of Pakistan at the time of the Kargil War, used terror tactics to silence critical press and the previously independent judiciary, for example storming the Supreme Court in order to force the Chief Justice out of office. Yassir Arafat, the president of the Palestinian Authority at the start of the latest conflicts with Israel, can be criticized on similar grounds. There was never a democratic election in the Philippines before the Philippine-American war. All the Mexican presidents at the time of the conflicts with the U.S., like Mariano Paredes y Arrillaga, took their power in coup d'etats. The nations in the War of the Pacific were ruled by Caudillos or had suffrage requirements like literacy or property that excluded a large part of the populations.

Liberal democracies before the late nineteenth century?

Whether the pre-modern states that once identified themselves as democracies fulfill modern criteria remains controversial. In Ancient Greece, such city-states did fight wars between each other (most noted is the Athenian expedition against Syracuse during the Peloponnesian War). Many do not deem Ancient Greek city-states as sufficiently democratic because of the large numbers of slaves and other non-voting inhabitants. It is estimated that only 16% of the population in Athens had the right to vote. There were also three great wars between Rome and Carthage; and the Roman republic sacked Athens. Similar questions arise about the persistent wars among Venice, Florence, Genoa, and other Renaissance city-states. These states were also not as democratic as modern democracies, but at least as much as Athens and more so than Syracuse.

An interesting case is the Polish-Lithuanian Commonwealth, which had some qualities of today's democracies and in which szlachta (the nobles), using Sejm (a parliament), blocked many monarchs' attempts to declare a war on other countries. Some scholars have put forward the Swiss Confederation (or parts of it) and the Six Iroquois Nations as early examples of communities of democratic states upholding the theory.

Deaths in battle

The rule of at least 1000 killed in battle excludes attacks by one democracy on another in such overwhelming force that there is no effective resistance, and thus few deaths in battle (some Indian Wars and small scale foreign interventions by the United States may be examples.)

Democracies have engaged in covert conflict resulting in a change of regime on the losing side. The British- and American-supported 1953 coup d'etat in Iran against Mohammed Mossadegh and the 1954 U.S.-backed coup in Guatemala, led by Carlos Castillo Armas as examples of such events. The rule also excludes these events.

There is at least one democracy which formally declared war on another when the United Kingdom declared war on Finland on December 6, 1941 in reaction to the Continuation War, when Finland allied with Germany in attacking the Soviet Union. However, the United Kingdom's only significant act of war happened prior to the declaration (a Royal Air Force raid on the port of Petsamo on July 31, 1941). However, Finland spent World War II fighting a totalitarian opponent who had attacked the nation, the United Kingdom and Finland for almost the whole of WWII carefully avoided attacking each other, and the casualties in the conflict with the United Kingdom were too few to be classified as a war statistically. The lavish material support the United Kingdom and the United States provided to Soviet Union raises the question if democracies can make war against other democracies through proxies.

Rummel's time limit

Rummel's version of the DOT has a requirement that the democratic states must be older than three years excludes the war between the French Second Republic and the Roman Republic (19th century). The First Balkan War is excluded if one considers the Ottoman Empire to have become democratic after the first election in November 1908 or when the constitution was amended so that the parliament could control the cabinet in April 1909. The war started in October 1912, which would be before four years had passed. Critics instead argue that democracy occurred in July 1908 when a constitution was introduced. It is also doubtful if the opposing Christian states fulfill the democratic criteria since the Kings continued to have extensive powers in all of them.

The time limit and and other requirements like democratic institutions and elections on both sides, also exclude civil wars within democracies over legitimacy or secession, such as the American Civil War, the Sonderbund war, the Anglo-Irish War and the Irish civil war which followed, and the 20th century civil wars in Colombia, Spain, Uruguay and Sri Lanka.

Correlation is not causation

A statistical association does not establish causality. Critics have thus argued that the peace may be explained by other factors in democratic states that are not related to democracy. Supporters of the DPT argue that many studies have controlled for such factors and that the DPT is still validated. For example, Bremer (1992, 1993) controlled for contiguity, power status, alliance ties, militarization, economic development, and power ratios. Maoz & Russett (1992, 1993) and Russett (1993) controlled for contiguity, alliance ties, economic wealth and growth, political stability, and power ratios.

Trade

Following Schumpeter, some hypothesize that the phenomenon is explained by the fact that democratic countries tend to be capitalist states, whose trade relations with one another create interdependence among them. This interdependence constrains the ability and willingness of democratic nations to go to war with each other due to the incurred costs in lost trade. However, one problem with this interpretation is the existence of non-democratic capitalist states, who often have made war with each other or with democratic states. However, a recent study shows that economically important trade has a substantively important pacifying effect which is independent of democracy. It also shows that democracy does have a pacifying effect independent of trade. This study also indicates that the DPT is not a significant factor unless both of the democracies have a GDP/capita of at least 1400 USD. Economic development below this may hinder the development of liberal institutions. .

Geographic isolation

Some critics have argued that few democracies mean that they are geographically isolated and thus unable to make war with each other. However, Maoz & Russet studied the period from 1945 and 1986 and discounted all dyads that did not involve a major power or nations that were not geographically continuous. The DPT was still validated. Bremer (1992) and other studies also support this conclusion. Glieditsch (1995) demonstrated that democratic dyads have not been more separated than non-democratic dyads. Supporters also note that today more than 50% of all nations are democratic .

The bloc peace theory

Joanne Gowa argues in Ballots and Bullets: The Elusive Democratic Peace, that the structure of the international political system during the Cold War was responsible for creating the illusion of a democratic peace. At about the same time many of today's democracies came into existence, the Cold War divided much of the world into two systems of institutionalized alliances. (Many states belonged to neither; chief among these was the People's Republic of China after 1961.) These critics claim the inter-democratic peace of the period is explained by a larger "bloc peace theory": they ascribe the inter-democratic peace of the period to this structure of blocs: almost all the democracies of the Cold War were members of the Western bloc, and the members of that bloc abstained from attacking one another in a collective effort to contain the bigger threat posed by Communism. Not only was the system of alliances produced by this common interest; also, once it had come into existence, the relations between two members of the bloc were not permitted to decline into full-scale war; the alliance provided their common allies with the interest and the leverage to prevent it.

Supporters of the DPT note that Bremer (1992), Maoz & Russett (1992, 1993), Russett (1993), Oneal et al (1996), Barbieri (1996a), Oneal & Russett (1997), and Oneal & Ray (1997) all have controlled for alliance ties in their statistical studies supporting the DPT, contradicting Gowa's theory.

Specific historic examples

During the Cold War

The bloc peace theory makes, in some ways, broader claims than DPT. For example, some skeptics of DPT argue that the Suex Crisis was suppressed in less than two weeks since Egypt was a marginal member of the Western bloc. This as confirmation that potential attacks on full members would have been stopped before they began. Even though Egypt was not a democracy, the Suez Canal treaties were supposed to bind her closely to Britain. However, it is doubtful that Egypt was an Western ally at all because Egypt had nationalized the canal, the US had stopped foreign aid, and Egypt had bought weapons from the Communist states.

The DPT supporters have argued that while Gowa only applied the theory that external threats stopped internal wars to the democratic Western nations, such a theory also predicts that there should have been no wars at all in the Western bloc, including no wars involving dictatorships, and no wars in the opposing Communist bloc .

There were several wars between Communist nations: the Soviet invasion of Afghanistan, the Ogaden War, and the Cambodian-Vietnamese War. However, Ethiopia and Somalia belonged to different blocs, even if both claimed to be socialist. There were also minor conflicts, not meeting the threshold of deaths, particularly the Sino-Soviet border conflict and the Prague spring. Another possible counter example is the 1956 Hungarian Revolution. However, many hold that (despite the Stalinist record of its chief) it was effectively a non-Communist regime and may have ceased to be part of the Warsaw pact bloc, becoming either a neutral or a Western power. However, Nagy was a Communist, had been an agent for the Soviet security apparatus earlier, and was installed by the Hungarian Communist Party.

Supporters of the DPT also argue that the critics thus seem to define "bloc" arbitrarily in order to avoid some exceptions for the Communist states, arguing that the Western world similarly had many different "blocs" but without having wars between democracies. For instance, France was antagonistic with the United States and expelled the NATO headquarters and all NATO forces from its territory; France, however, did not withdrew formally from NATO, and retained or even increased its ties to the other nations in the European Union. Supporters also note that the neutral democratic Western nations Sweden, Ireland, Austria, and Schwitzerland were not involved in wars with other democratic nations. If all capitalist democracies were to be considered part of a common bloc, then it may also be argued that China was still part of a common Communist bloc, and thus that the Sino-Vietnamese War is another counter example to the bloc peace theory.

There were many large scale wars involving dictatorships and the absence of wars between democracies in the Third World during the same period, which supports the DPT. However, there were few democracies there and then. On the other hand,many of the Western nations had or could easily develop the military capability to attack democracies in the Third World but did not.

There were wars in the Western bloc between democracies and dictatorships, arguably disproving the bloc peace theory. One example is the Turkish invasion of Cyprus in 1974, at a time when Cyprus had British military bases and close ties to Turkey's NATO partner Greece. Another is the Football War. However, the U.S. put pressure on the combatants to stop the Football War which fits the bloc peace theory. A third is the 1965 U.S. invasion of the Dominican Republic. The 1967 Six Day War and the 1973 Yom Kippur War may also be wars within the Western bloc, because Iraq belonged to CENTO and Israel received extensive aid from the U.S. Bloc peace theory supporters claim that CENTO was not a functioning organization and note that The Soviet-Iraqi Treaty of Friendship was signed in 1972. Still another examples are the two Gulf Wars, in which Arabic nations fought each other despite belonging to the Arab League and OPEC. All of these wars had more than 1000 military casualties . The Falklands War almost qualify (936 causalities).

Before the Cold War

Critics of the DPT argue that before the Cold War, the limited period during which there was more than one non-allied democratic Great Power includes several crises between them, including the Fashoda crisis, between the United Kingdom and France, and the Venezuela crisis between the United Kingdom and the United States. These were conducted as fiercely as many diplomatic conflicts involving a non-democratic state; and war was popular on both sides.

On the other hand, even when there were conflicts, democracies did not make war with each other. Also, in the nineteenth century, much of the world was divided into blocs by the imperialist powers. This was often strictly regulated as when England and Russia divided Persia into two spheres of influence. Numerous wars occurred in these blocs, arguably contradicting the bloc peace theory, both by the imperialist powers when they extended direct rule and also between minor states in these blocs. For example, an incomplete list of wars in India after England had become the dominant European power includes three Anglo-Maratha Wars, four Anglo-Mysore Wars, two Anglo-Sikh Wars, three Anglo-Afghan Wars, the Anglo-Nepalese War, the Anglo-Bhutanese War, and three Anglo-Burmese Wars.

There were numerous wars in Latin America, despite belonging to an U.S. dominated bloc after the Monroe doctrine. This bloc was frequently threatened by the other imperialist blocs and sometimes direct military action occurred, like the French military invasion of Mexico. Examples of large scale wars in Latin America in this period include the War of the Triple Alliance, the War of the Pacific, the War of the Peruvian-Bolivian Confederation, the Mexican-American War, and the Chaco War. There werr also several betrayls of formal treaties within blocs during WWII. Examples include the wars of Finland, Italy, Bulgaria, Roumania, and Hungary on their German ally in WWII and the German invasion of the Soviet Union despite the Molotov-Ribbentrop Nonaggression Pact and its secret extensions.

After the Cold War

Supporters also argue that external causes cannot explain the continued peace between democracies after the end of the Cold War. Critics respond that the European Union contains some of those democracies capable of maintaining a major war, and is also an institutionalized alliance. However, even those European states still have separate militaries and to a large degree separate foreign policy. There are also many democracies outside Europe .

References

  • Beck, Nathaniel, and Richard Tucker. Democracy and Peace: General Law or Limited Phenomenon? Midwest Political Science Association: April 1998.
  • Correlates of War Project
  • Brown, Michael E., Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller. Debating the Democratic Peace. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996.
  • Doyle, Michael W. Ways of War and Peace. New York: W.W. Norton, 1997.
  • Gowa, Joanne. Ballots and Bullets: The Elusive Democratic Peace. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999.
  • Huth, Paul K., et al. The Democratic Peace and Territorial Conflict in the Twentieth Century. Cambridge University Press: 2003. ISBN 0521805082.
  • Levy, Jack S. “Domestic Politics and War.” Journal of Interdisciplinary History, Vol. 18, No. 4, (Spring, 1988), pp. 653-673.
  • Lipson, Charles. Reliable Partners: How Democracies Have Made a Separate Peace. Princeton University Press: 2003. ISBN 0691113904.
  • Polity IV Project: Political Regime Characteristics and Transitions, 1800-2002
  • Ray, James Lee. Democracy and International Conflict: An Evaluation of the Democratic Peace Proposition. University of South Carolina Press: 1998. ISBN 1570032416.
  • Ray, James Lee. Does Democracy Cause Peace? Annual Review of Political Science 1998:1, 27-46
  • Rummel, R.J. Power Kills: Democracy As a Method of Nonviolence. Transaction Publishers: 2003. ISBN 0765805235.
  • Russett, Bruce. Grasping the Democratic Peace. Princeton University Press: 1994. ISBN 0691001642.

External links

Supportive

Critical

See also

Categories:
Democratic peace theory: Difference between revisions Add topic